This prompts the question: How far would we get if we started with a collection of subsets possessing these above-mentioned properties and proceeded to define everything in terms of them?
We will call any collection of sets on X satisfying these properties a topology. In the following section, we also seek to give alternative ways of describing this important collection of sets.
|
|
Occasionally, arguments can be simplified when the sets involved are not ``over-described''. In particular, it is sometimes suffices to use sets which contain open sets but are not necessarily open. We call such sets neighborhoods.
Definition 2 Given a topological space (X, T) with x Î X, then N Í X is said to be a (T)-neighbourhood of x Û $ open set G with x Î G Í N.
It follows then that a set U Í X is open iff for every x Î U, there exists a neighbourhood Nx of x contained in U. (Check this!)
Lemma 1
Let (X, T) be a topological space and, for each x Î X, let
N(x) be the family of neighbourhoods of x. Then
(i) U Î N(x) Þ x Î U.
(ii) N(x) is closed under finite intersections.
(iii) U Î N(x) and U Í V Þ V Î N(x).
(iv) U Î N(x) Þ $ W Î N(x) such
that W Í U and W Î N(y) for each y Î W.
|
|
In fact, the only nhd of x is X.
It often happens that the open sets of a space can be very complicated and yet they can all be described using a selection of fairly simple special ones. When this happens, the set of simple open sets is called a base or subbase (depending on how the description is to be done). In addition, it is fortunate that many topological concepts can be characterized in terms of these simpler base or subbase elements.
Definition 3 Let (X,T) be a topological space. A family B Í T is called a base for (X,T) if and only if every non-empty open subset of X can be represented as a union of a subfamily of B.
It is easily verified that B Í T is a base for (X, T) if and only if whenever x Î G Î T, $B Î B such that x Î B Í G.
Clearly, a topological space can have many bases.
Lemma 2
If B is a family of subsets of a set X such that
then B is a base for a unique topology on X.
Conversely, any base B for a topological space (X,T) satisfies
(B1) and (B2).
(B1) for any B1, B2 Î B and every point x Î B1 ÇB2,
there exists B3 Î B with x Î B3 Í B1 ÇB2, and
(B2) for every x Î X, there exists B Î B such that x Î B,
Proof (Exercise!)
Definition 4 Let (X,T) be a topological space. A family S Í T is called a subbase for (X,T) if and only if the family of all finite intersections Çi = 1kUi, where Ui Î S for i = 1,2,¼,k is a base for (X,T).
From the above examples, it follows that for a set X one can select in many different ways a family T such that (X,T) is a topological space. If T1 and T2 are two topologies for X and T2 Í T1, then we say that the topology T1 is finer than the topology T2, or that T2 is coarser than the topology T1. The discrete topology for X is the finest one; the trivial topology is the coarsest.
If X is an arbitrary infinite set with distinct points x and y, then one can readily verify that the topologies Á(x) and Á(y) are incomparable i.e. neither is finer than the other.
By generating a topology for X, we mean selecting a family T of subsets of X which satisfies conditions (T1)-(T3). Often it is more convenient not to describe the family T of open sets directly. The concept of a base offers an alternative method of generating topologies.
(I) the (Euclidean) open discs in the upper half-plane;
(II) the (Euclidean) open discs tangent to the `edge' of the L,
together with the point of tangency.
Note If yn ® y in L, then
(i) y not on `edge': same as Euclidean convergence.
(ii) y on the `edge': same as Euclidean, but yn must approach y
from `inside'. Thus, for example, yn = ([1/n],0) \not ® (0,0)!
A subset of a topological space inherits a topology of its own, in an obvious way:
Definition 5 Given a topological space (X, T) with A Í X, then the family TA = {A ÇG:G Î T } is a topology for A, called the subspace (or relative or induced) topology for A. (A, TA) is called a subspace of (X, T).
Example
The interval I = [0,1] with its natural (Euclidean) topology is a (closed)
subspace of (R, Á).
Warning: Although this definition, and several of the results which flow from it, may suggest that subspaces in general topology are going to be `easy' in the sense that a lot of the structure just gets traced onto the subset, there is unfortunately a rich source of mistakes here also: because we are handling two topologies at once. When we inspect a subset B of A, and refer to it as 'open' (or 'closed', or a 'neighbourhood' of some point p .... ) we must be exceedingly careful as to which topology is intended. For instance, in the previous example, [0,1] itself is open in the subspace topology on I but, of course, not in the 'background' topology of R. In such circumstances, it is advisable to specify the topology being used each time by saying T-open, TA-open, and so on.
Definition 6 Given a topological space (X,T) with F Í X, then F is said to be T-closed iff its complement X \F is T-open.
From De Morgan's Laws and properties (T1)-(T3) of open sets, we infer that the family F of closed sets of a space has the following properties:
(F1) X Î F and Æ Î F
(F2) F is closed under finite union
(F3) F is closed under arbitrary intersection.
Sets which are simultaneously closed and open in a topological space are sometimes referred to as clopen sets. For example, members of the base B = { [x,r):x, r Î R, x < r, r rational } for the Sorgenfrey line are clopen with respect to the topology generated by B. Indeed, for the discrete space (X, D), every subset is clopen.
Definition 7
If (X,T) is a topological space and A Í X, then
A
T
= Ç{F Í X: A Í F and F is closed}
Evidently, [`A]T (or [`A] when there is no danger of ambiguity) is the smallest closed subset of X which contains A. Note that A is closed Û A = [`A].
Lemma 3
If (X, T) is a topological space with A, B Í X, then
(i) [`(Æ)] = Æ
(ii) A Í [`A]
(iii) [`([`A])] = [`A]
(iv) [`(AÈB)] = [`A] È[`B].
Theorem 1 Given a topological space with A Í X, then x Î [`A] iff for each nhd U of x, U ÇA ¹ Æ.
Proof
$\Rightarrow$: Let x Î [`A] and let U be a nhd of x; then
there exists open G with x Î G Í U. If U ÇA = Æ,
then G ÇA = Æ and so A Í X \G Þ [`A] Í X \G whence x Î X \G, thereby contradicting the assumption that
U ÇA = Æ.
$\Leftarrow$: If x Î X \[`A], then X \[`A] is an open nhd of x so that, by
hypothesis, (X \[`A]) ÇA ¹ Æ, which is a contradiction (i.e., a false statement).
(i) For an arbitrary infinite set X with the cofinite topology C,
the closed sets are just the finite ones together with X. So for any
A Í X,
|
(ii) For an arbitrary uncountable set X with the cocountable topology L,
the closed sets are the countable ones and X itself. Note that if we let
X = R, then [`[0,1]] = R! (In the usual Euclidean topology,
[`[0,1]] = [0,1].)
(iii) For the space (X, Tx) defined earlier, if Æ Ì A Í X, then
|
(iv) For (X, Á(x)) with A Í X,
|
(v) For (X, E(x)) with Æ Ì A Í X,
|
(vi) In (X, D), every subset equals its own closure.
Because many properties of spaces are preserved by continuous functions, spaces related by a bijection (one-to-one and onto function) which is continuous in both directions will have many properties in common. These properties are identified as topological properties. Spaces so related are called homeomorphic.
Definition 8 Let (X, T) and (Y, S) be topological spaces; a mapping f:X® Y is called continuous iff f-1(U) Î T for each U Î S i.e. the inverse image of any open subset of Y is open in X.
Examples
(i) If (X, D) is discrete and (Y, S) is an arbitrary
topological space, then any function f:X ® Y is continuous!
Again, if (X, T) is an arbitrary topological space and
(Y, T0) is trivial, any mapping
g:X ® Y is continuous.
(ii) If (X, T), (Y, S) are arbitrary topological spaces
and
f:X ® Y is a constant map, then f is continuous.
(iii) Let X be an arbitrary set having more than two elements, with x Î X. Let T = I(x),
S = Tx in the definition of continuity; then the identity
map idX:X ® X is
continuous. However, if we interchange T
with S so that T = Tx and S = Á(x), then
idX:X ® X is not continuous! Note that idX:(X, T1) ® (X, T2)
is continuous if and only if T1 is finer than T2.
Theorem 2 If (X1, T1), (X2, T2) and (X3, T3) are topological spaces and h:X1 ® X2 and g:X2 ® X3 are continuous, then g°h:X1 ® X3 is continuous.
Proof Immediate.
There are several different ways to 'recognise' continuity for a mapping
between topological spaces, of which the next theorem indicates two of the
most useful apart from the definition itself:
Theorem 3
Let f be a mapping from a topological space (X1, T1) to a
topological space (X2, T2). The following statements are
equivalent:
(i) f is continuous,
(ii) the preimage under f of each closed subset of X2 is closed in X1,
(iii) for every subset A of X1, f([`A]) Í [`f(A)].
Definition 9 Let (X, T), (Y, S) be topological spaces and let h:X ® Y be bijective. Then h is a homeomorphism iff h is continuous and h-1 is continuous. If such a map exists, (X, T) and (Y, S) are called homeomorphic.
Such a map has the property that
|
Example
For every space (X, T), the identity mapping idX:X ® X
is a homeomorphism.
A property of topological spaces which when possessed by a space is also possessed by every space homeomorphic to it is called a topological invariant. We shall meet some examples of such properties later.
One can readily verify that if f is a homeomorphism, then the inverse mapping f-1 is also a homeomorphism and that the composition g °f of two homeomorphisms f and g is again a homeomorphism. Thus, the relation `X and Y are homeomorphic' is an equivalence relation.
In general, it may be quite difficult to demonstrate that two spaces are homeomorphic (unless a homeomorphism is obvious or can easily be discovered). For example, to verify that (R, Á) is homeomorphic to (0,1) with its induced metric topology, it is necessary to demonstrate, for instance, that h:(0,1) ® R where h(x) = [(2x-1)/(x(x-1))] is a homeomorphism.
It is often easier to show that two spaces are not homeomorphic: simply exhibit an invariant which is possessed by one space and not the other.
Example
The spaces (X, Á(x)) and (X, E(x)) are not homeomorphic
since, for example, (X, Á(x)) has the topological invariant `each
nhd is open' while (X, E(x)) does not.
Definition 10 A sequence (xn) in a topological space (X, T) is said to converge to a point x Î X iff (xn) eventually belongs to every nhd of x i.e. iff for every nhd U of x, there exists n0 Î N such that xn Î U for all n ³ n0.
Caution
We learnt that, for metric spaces, sequential convergence was adequate to describe the topology of such spaces (in the sense that the basic primitives of `open set', `neighbourhood', `closure' etc. could be fully characterised in terms of sequential convergence). However, for general topological spaces, sequential convergence fails. We illustrate:
(i) Limits are not always unique. For example, in (X, T0),
each sequence (xn) converges to every x Î X.
(ii) In R with the cocountable topology L, [0,1] is not
closed and so G = (-¥,0) È(1,¥) is not open - yet if xn ® x where x Î G, then Assignment 1 shows that xn Î G for
all sufficiently large n.
Further, 2 Î [`[0,1]]L, yet no sequence in [0,1] can
approach 2. So another characterisation fails to carry over from metric space
theory.
Finally, every L-convergent sequence of points in [0,1] must have its limit in [0,1] - but [0,1] is not closed (in L)!
Hence, to discuss topological convergence thoroughly, we need to develop a new basic set-theoretic tool which generalises the notion of sequence. It is called a net - we shall return to this later.
Definition 11 A topological space (X, T) is called metrizable iff there exists a metric d on X such that the topology Td induced by d coincides with the original topology T on X.
The investigations above show that (X, T0) and (R, L) are examples of non-metrizable spaces. However, the discrete space (X,D) is metrizable, being induced by the discrete metric
|
We explained in the previous chapter what a topological property (homeomorphic invariant) is but gave few good examples. We now explore some of the most important ones. Recurring themes will be:
If A is a subspace of a space (X, T), U is an open cover for A iff U is a cover for A such that each member of U is open in X.
The classic theorem of Heine-Borel-Lebesgue asserts that, in R, every open cover of a closed bounded subset has a finite subcover. This theorem has extraordinarily profound consequences and like most good theorems, its conclusion has become a definition.
Definition 1 (X, T) is said to be compact iff every open cover of X has a finite subcover.
Theorem 1 [Alexander's Subbase Theorem] Let S be any subbase for (X,T). If every open cover of X by members of S has a finite subcover, then X is compact.
The proof of this deep result is an application of Zorn's lemma, and is not an exercise for the faint-hearted!
(i) (R, Á) is not compact, for consider U = { (-n,n): n Î N }. Similarly, (C, Tusual) is not compact.
(ii) (0,1) is not compact, for consider U = { ([1/n],1) :n ³ 2 }.
(iii) (X, C) is compact, for any X.
(iv) Given x Î X, (X, E(x)) is compact; (X, I(x)) is not compact unless X is finite.
(v) T finite for any X Þ (X, T) compact.
(vi) X finite, T any topology for X Þ (X, T)
compact.
(vii) X infinite Þ (X, D) not compact.
(viii) Given (X, T), if (xn) is a sequence in X convergent to
x, then { xn:n Î N } È{x} is compact.
We call a subset A of (X,T) a compact subset when the subspace (A, TA) is a compact space. It's a nuisance to have to look at TA in order to decide on this. It would be easier to use the original T. Thankfully, we can!
Lemma 1 A is a compact subset of (X,T) iff every T-open cover of A has a finite subcover.
Proof Exercise.
Lemma 2 Compactness is closed-hereditary and preserved by continuous maps.
Proof Exercise.
Example
The unit circle in R2 is compact; indeed, paths in any space are compact.
In any metric space (M, d), every compact subset K is closed and bounded:
(bounded, since given any x0 Î M,
|
Neither half is valid in all topological spaces;
Further, in a metric space, a closed bounded subset needn't be compact (e.g. consider M with the discrete metric and let A Í M be infinite; then A is closed, bounded (since A Í B(x,2) = M for any x Î M), yet it is certainly not compact! Alternatively, the subspace (0,1) is closed (in itself), bounded, but not compact.)
However, the Heine-Borel theorem asserts that such is the case for R and Rn; the following is a special case of the theorem:
Theorem 2 Every closed, bounded interval [a,b] in R is compact.
Proof Let U be any open cover of [a,b] and let K = { x Î [a,b]: [a,x] is covered by a finite subfamily of U}. Note that if x Î K and a £ y £ x, then y Î K. Clearly, K ¹ Æ since a Î K. Moreover, given x Î K, there exists dx > 0 such that [x,x+ dx) Í K (since x Î some open U Î chosen finite subcover of U). Since K is bounded, k* = supK exists.
(i) | k* Î K | : Choose U Î U such that k* Î U; then there exists e > 0 such that (k*-e,k*] Í U. Since there exists x Î K such that k*-e < x < k*, k* Î K. |
(ii) | k* = b | : If k* < b, choose U Î U with k* Î U and note that [k*,k*+d) Í U for some d > 0 -contradiction! |
Note An alternative proof [Willard, Page 116] is to invoke the connected nature of [a,b] by showing K is clopen in [a,b].
Theorem 3 Any continuous map from a compact space into a metric space is bounded.
Proof Immediate.
Corollary 1 If (X, T) is compact and f:X ® R is continuous, then f is bounded and attains its bounds.
Proof Clearly, f is bounded. Let m = supf(X) and l = inff(X); we must prove that m Î f(X) and l Î f(X). Suppose that m \not Î f(X). Since [`f(X)] = f(X), then there exists e > 0 such that (m-e,m+e) Çf(X) = Æ i.e. for all x Î X, f(x) £ m-e¼contra!
Similarly, if l \not Î f(X), then there exists e > 0 such that [l,l+e) Çf(X) = Æ whence l+e is a lower bound for f(X)!
Definition 2 A topological space (X, T) is said to be sequentially compact if and only if every sequence in X has a convergent subsequence.
Recall from Chapter 1 the definition of convergence of sequences in topological spaces and the cautionary remarks accompanying it. There we noted that, contrary to the metric space situation, sequences in topology can have several different limits! Consider, for example, (X,T0) and (R,L). In the latter space, if xn ® l, then xn = l for all n ³ some n0. Thus the sequence 1,[1/2], [1/4], [1/8], ¼ does not converge in (R,L)!
Lemma 3 Sequential compactness is closed-hereditary and preserved by continuous maps.
Proof Exercise.
We shall prove in the next section that in metric spaces, sequential compactness and compactness are equivalent!
Definition 3 Given a topological space (X,T), a subset A of X and x Î X, x is said to be an accumulation point of A iff every neighbourhood of x contains infinitely many points of A.
Lemma 4 Given a compact space (X,T) with an infinite subset A of X, then A has an accumulation point.
Proof Suppose not; then for each x Î X, there exists a neighbourhood Nx of x such that Nx ÇA is (at most) finite; the family { Nx:x Î X } is an open cover of X and so has a finite subcover { Nxi:i = 1, ¼,n }. But A Í X and A is infinite, whence
|
Lemma 5 Given a sequentially compact metric space (M,d) and e > 0, there is a finite number of open balls, radius e, which cover M.
Proof Suppose not and that for some e > 0, there exists no finite family of open balls, radius e, covering M. We derive a contradiction by constructing a sequence (xn) inductively such that d(xm,xn) ³ e for all n, m (n ¹ m), whence no subsequence is even Cauchy!
Let x1 Î M and suppose inductively that x1, ¼,xk have been chosen in M such that d(xi,xj) ³ e for all i, j £ k,i ¹ j.By hypothesis, {B(xi,e):i = 1,¼,k } is not an (open) cover of M and so there exists xk+1 Î M such that d(xk+1,xi) ³ e for 1 £ i £ k. We thus construct the required sequence (xn), which clearly has no convergent subsequence.
Theorem 4 A metric space is compact iff it is sequentially compact.
Proof
$\Rightarrow :$ Suppose (M,d) is compact. Given any sequence
(xn) in M, either A = {x1,x2, ¼} is finite or it is infinite. If
A is finite, there must be at least one point l in A which occurs
infinitely often in the sequence and its occurrences form a subsequence
converging to l. If A is infinite, then by the previous lemma there exists
x Î X such that every neighbourhood of x contains infinitely many points
of A.
For each k Î w, B(x,[1/k]) contains infinitely many xn's:
select one, call it xnk, making sure that nk > nk-1 > nk-2 ¼. We have a subsequence (xn1, xn2, ¼, xnk, ¼)
so that d(x,xnk) < [1/k] ® 0 i.e. xnk ® x. Thus in either case there exists a convergent subsequence and
so (M,d) is sequentially compact.
$\Leftarrow :$ Conversely, suppose (M,d) is sequentially compact
and not compact. Then there exists some open cover {Gi:i Î I}
of M having no finite subcover. By Lemma 2.1.4, with e = [1/n] (n Î w), we can cover M by a finite number of
balls of radius [1/n]. For each n, there has to be one of these, say
B(xn,[1/n]), which cannot be covered by any finite number of the sets
Gi. The sequence (xn) must have a convergent subsequence (xnk)
which converges to a limit l. Yet {Gi:i Î I} covers M, so l Î some Gi0, say.
As k ® ¥, xnk ® l; but also [1/(nk)] ® 0 and 1/nk is the radius of the ball centred on xnk. So eventually B(xnk,[1/(nk)]) is inside Gi0, contradictory to their choice! (More rigorously, there exists m Î w such that B(l,[2/m]) Í Gi0. Now B(l,[1/m]) contains xnk for all k ³ k0 say, so choose k ³ k0 such that nk ³ m. Then B(xnk,[1/(nk)]) Í B(l, [2/m]) Í Gi0.) Hence, M is compact.
Recall that a map f:(X1,d1) ® (X2,d2), where (Xi,di) is a metric space for each i, is uniformly continuous on Xi if given any e > 0,$d > 0 such that d1(x,y) < d for x,y Î X1 Þ d2(f(x),f(y)) < e.
Ordinary continuity of f is a local property, while uniform continuity is a global property since it says something about the behaviour of f over the whole space X1. Since compactness allows us to pass from the local to the global, the next result is not surprising:
Theorem 5 If (X,d) is a compact metric space and f:X ® R is continuous, then f is uniformly continuous on X.
Note Result holds for any metric space codomain.
Proof Let e > 0; since f is continuous,
for each
x Î X, $dx > 0 such that d(x,y) < 2 dx
Þ |f(x) -f(y)| < [(e)/2]. The family {Bdx(x):x Î X } is an open cover of X and so has a finite subcover
{Bdxi(xi):i = 1,¼,n} of X. Let d = min{dxi:i = 1,¼,n}; then, given x,y Î X such that d(x,y) < d, it follows that |f(x) -f(y)| < e
(for x Î Bdxi(xi) for some i, whence d(x,xi) < dxi and so d(y,xi) £ d(y,x) + d(x,xi) < d+ dxi £ 2dxi Þ |f(y) -f(xi)| < [(e)/2].
Thus |f(x)-f(y)| £ |f(x) -f(xi)| + |f(xi) - f(y)| < [(e)/2] +[(e)/2] = e).
Note Compactness is not a necessary condition on the domain for uniform continuity. For example, for any metric space (X,d), let f:X ® X be the identity map. Then f is easily seen to be uniformly continuous on X.
Definition 4 A topological space (X,T) is locally compact iff each point of X has a compact neighbourhood.
Clearly, every compact space is locally compact. However, the converse is not true.
Examples
(i) With X infinite, the discrete space (X,D) is clearly locally
compact (for each x Î X, {x} is a compact neighbourhood of x!) but
not compact.
(ii) With X infinite and x Î X, (X, Á(x)) is locally compact
(but not compact).
(iii) (R,Á) is locally compact (x Î R Þ [x-1,x+1] is a
compact neighbourhood of x).
(iv) The set of rational numbers Q with its usual topology is not a
locally compact
space, for suppose otherwise; then 0 has a compact neighbourhood C in Q so
we can choose e > 0 such that J = QÇ[-e, e] Í C. Now J is closed in (compact) C and is therefore compact in
R. Thus, J must be closed in R-but [`J]R = [-e,e]!
Lemma 6
(i) Local compactness is closed-hereditary.
(ii) Local compactness is preserved by continuous open maps - it is not
preserved by continuous maps in general. Consider idQ:(Q,D) ® (Q,ÁQ) which is continuous and onto; (Q, D) is
locally compact while (Q, ÁQ) isn't!
Definition 5
A topological space (X, T) is said to be
(i) Lindelöf iff every open cover of X has a countable
subcover
(ii) countably compact iff every countable open cover of X has
a finite subcover.
However, for metric spaces, or more generally, metrizable spaces, the conditions
compact, countably compact and sequentially compact are equivalent.
Note Second countable Þ separable; separable + metrizable
Þ second countable ... and so in metrizable spaces, second
countability and separability are equivalent.
A partition of (X, T) means a pair of disjoint, non-empty, T-open subsets whose union is X. Notice that, since these sets are complements of one another, they are both closed as well as both open. Indeed, the definition of 'partition' is not affected by replacing the term 'open' by 'closed'.
Definition 6
A connected space (X, T) is one which has no partition.
(Otherwise, (X, T) is said to be disconnected.)
If Æ ¹ A Í (X, T), we call A a connected set
in X whenever (A, TA) is a connected space.
Lemma 7 (X, T) is connected iff X and Æ are the only subsets which are clopen.
(i) (X, T0) is connected.
(ii) (X, D) cannot be connected unless |X| = 1. (Indeed the only
connected subsets are the singletons!)
(iii) The Sorgenfrey line Rs is disconnected (for [x,¥) is clopen!).
(iv) The subspace Q of (R, Á) is not connected because
|
Lemma 8 Æ Ì A Í (X, T) is not connected iff there exist T-open sets G, H such that A Í G ÈH, A ÇG ¹ Æ, A ÇH ¹ Æ and A ÇG ÇH = Æ. (Again, we can replace 'open' by 'closed' here.)
Proof Exercise.
Note By an interval in R, we mean any subset I such that whenever a < b < c and whenever a Î I and c Î I then b Î I. It is routine to check that the only ones are (a,b), [a,b], [a,b), (a,b], [a, ¥), (a, ¥), (-¥,b), (-¥,b], (-¥,¥) = R and {a} for real a, b, a < b where appropriate.
It turns out that these are exactly the connected subsets of (R, Á):-
Lemma 9 In R, if [a,b] = F1 ÈF2 where F1, F2 are both closed and a Î F1, b Î F2 then F1 ÇF2 ¹ Æ.
Proof Exercise.
Theorem 6 Let Æ Ì I Í (R, Á). Then I is connected iff I is an interval.
Proof
$\Rightarrow$: If I is not an interval, then there exist
a < b < c with a Î I, b \not Î I and c Î I. Take A = I Ç(-¥,b) and B = I Ç(b, ¥). Then A ÈB = I, A ÇB = Æ, A ¹ Æ, B ¹ Æ, A Ì I, B Ì I and A, B are both open in I i.e. A and B partition I and so
I is not connected.
$\Leftarrow$: Suppose I is not connected and that I is an
interval. By the `closed' version of Lemma 2.3.2, there exist closed
subsets K1, K2 of R such that I Í K1 ÈK2, I ÇK1 ¹ Æ, I ÇK2 ¹ Æ and I ÇK1 ÇK2 = Æ. Select a Î I ÇK1, b Î I ÇK2; without loss of
generality, a < b. Then [a,b] Í I so that [a,b] = ([a,b] ÇK1) È([a,b] ÇK2), whence by Lemma 2.3.2, Æ ¹ [a,b] ÇK1 ÇK2 Í I ÇK1 ÇK2 = Æ!
Lemma 10 Connectedness is preserved by continuous maps.
Proof Exercise.
Corollary 2 [Intermediate Value Theorem] If f:[a,b] ® R is continuous and f(a) < y < f(b), then y must be a value of f.
Proof Exercise.
Corollary 3 [Fixed point theorem for [0,1]] If f:[0,1] ® [0,1] is continuous, then it has a `fixed point' i.e. there exists some x Î [0,1] such that f(x) = x.
Proof Consider g(x) = f(x)-x. Then g:[0,1] ® R is continuous. Further, g(0) = f(0) ³ 0 and g(1) = f(1)-1 £ 0 so that 0 is intermediate between g(0) and g(1). Thus, by the Intermediate Value Theorem, there exists x Î [0,1] such that 0 = g(x) = f(x)-x i.e. such that f(x) = x.
Note Given continuous h:[a,b] ® [a,b], it follows that h has a fixed point since [a,b] @ [0,1] and `every continuous function has a fixed point' is a homeomorphic invariant.
Lemma 11 Let (X,T) be disconnected with Æ Ì Y Ì X, Y clopen. If A is any connected subset of X, then A Í Y or A Í X \Y.
Proof If A ÇY ¹ Æ ¹ A Ç(X \Y), then Æ Ì A ÇY Ì A and A ÇY is clopen in A. Thus, A is not connected! It follows that either A ÇY = Æ or A ÇX \Y = Æ i.e. either A Í X \Y or A Í Y.
Lemma 12 If the family {Ai:i Î I} of connected subsets of a space (X,T) has a non-empty intersection, then its union Èi Î IAi is connected.
Proof Suppose not and that there exists a non-empty proper clopen subset Y of Èi Î IAi. Then for each i Î I, either Ai Í Y or Ai Í Èi Î IAi \Y. However if for some j, Aj Í Y, then Ai Í Y for each i Î I (since Çi Î IAi ¹ Æ) which implies that Èi Î IAi Í Y!
Similarly, if for some k Î I, Ak Í Èi Î IAi \Y, then Èi Î IAi Í Èi Î IAi \Y!
Corollary 4 Given a family {Ci:i Î I} of connected subsets of a space (X,T), if B Í X is also connected and B ÇCi ¹ Æ for all i Î I, then B È(Èi Î ICi) is connected.
Proof Take Ai = B ÈCi in Lemma 2.3.3.
Lemma 13 If A is a connected subset of a space (X,T) and A Í B Í [`A]T, then B is a connected subset.
Proof If B is not connected, then there exists Æ Ì Y Ì B which is clopen in B . By Lemma 2.3.3, either A Í Y or A Í B \Y. Suppose A Í Y (a similar argument suffices for A Í B \Y); then [`A]T Í [`Y]T and so B \Y = B Ç(B \Y) = [`A]TB Ç(B \Y) Í [`Y]TB Ç(B \Y) = Y Ç(B \Y) = Æ - a contradiction!
Definition 7
Let (X, T) be a topological space with x Î X; we define the
component of x, Cx, in (X, T) to be the union of all connected
subsets of X which contain x i.e.
Cx = È{ A Í X:x Î A and A is connected }.
For each x Î X, it follows from Lemma 2.3.3 that Cx is the maximum connected subset of X which contains x. Also it is clear that if x, y Î X, either Cx = Cy or Cx ÇCy = Æ (for if z Î Cx ÇCy, then Cx ÈCy Í Cz Í Cx ÇCy whence Cx = Cy( = Cz)). Thus we may speak of the components of a space (X, T) (without reference to specific points of X): they partition the space into connected closed subsets (by Lemma 2.3.3) and are precisely the maximal connected subsets of X.
Examples
(i) If (X, T) is connected, (X, T) has only one component,
namely X!
(ii) For any discrete space, the components are the singletons.
(iii) In Q (with its usual topology), the components are the singletons.
(Thus, components need not be open.)
Definition 8 A space (X, T) is totally disconnected iff the only connected subsets of X are the singletons (equivalently, the components of (X, T) are the singletons).
Thus, by the previous examples, we see that the space Q of rationals, the space R \Q of irrationals and any discrete space are all totally disconnected. Further, the Sorgenfrey line Rs is totally disconnected.
Definition 9 A topological space (X, T) is pathwise connected iff for any x, y Î X, there exists a continuous function f:[0,1] ® X such that f(0) = x and f(1) = y. Such a function f is called a path from x to y.
Theorem 7 Every pathwise connected space is connected.
Proof Let (X, T) be pathwise connected and let a Î X; for every x Î X, there exists a path px:[0,1] ® X from a to x. Then, for each x Î X, px([0,1]) is connected; moreover, pa(0) = a Î Çx Î Xpx([0,1]) so that by Lemma 2.3.3, X = Èx Î Xpx([0,1]) is connected.
Note well The converse is false. Consider the following example, the topologist's sine curve :
|
(for suppose, w.l.o.g., there exists a path p:[0,1] ® X with p(0) = ([1/(p)],0) and p(1) = (0,0). Then p1°p, being continuous, must take all values between 0 and [1/(p)], in particular [1/((2n+[1/2])p)] for each n i.e. there exists tn Î [0,1] such that p1°p(tn) = [1/((2n+[1/2])p)] for each n. Thus, p(tn) = ([1/((2n+[1/2])p)],1) ® (0,1) as n ® ¥. Now tn Î [0,1] for all n which implies that there exists a subsequence (tnk) in [0,1] with tnk ® l. Then p(tnk) ® p(l) and so p1°p(tnk) ® 0. Thus p(l) = (0,y) for some y, whence y = 0 (since p(l) Î X)!)
Definition 10
A topological space is said to be
(i) separable iff it has a countable dense subset.
(ii) completely separable (equivalently,second countable) iff it has
a countable base.
(i) (R, Á) is separable (since [`Q] = R).
(ii) (X, C) is separable for any X.
(iii) (R, L) is not separable.
Theorem 8
(i) Complete separability implies separability.
(ii) The converse is true in metric spaces.
Theorem 9
(i) Complete separability is hereditary.
(ii) Separability is not hereditary.
(Consider the `included point' topology
Á(0) on R; then (R, Á(0)) is separable, since
[` {0}] = R. However, R \{0} is not separable
because it is discrete.)
Separability does not imply complete separability since, for example,
(R, Á(0)) is separable but not completely separable.(Suppose
there exists a countable base B for its topology. Given x ¹ 0,
{0,x } is an open neighbourhood of x and so there exists Bx Î B such that x Î Bx Í { 0,x }.Thus Bx = {0,x } i.e.
B is uncountable ... contradiction!
Theorem 10 Separability is preserved by continuous maps.
Proof Exercise.
Note Complete separability is not preserved by continuous maps.
In Chapter 1, we defined limits of sequences in a topological space (X, T) so as to assimilate the metric definition. We noted, however, that not everything we knew about this idea in metric spaces is valid in topological spaces.
We will examine two main ways around this difficulty:
The following important results are probably familiar to us in the context of metric spaces, or at least in the setting of the real line, R.
Theorem 1 Given (X,T), A Í X, p Î X: if there exists some sequence of points of A tending to p, then p Î [`A].
Theorem 2 Given (X,T), A Í X: if A is closed, then A includes the limit of every convergent sequence of points of A.
Theorem 3 Given f:(X,T) ® (Y,T¢): if f is continuous, then f `preserves limits of sequences' i.e. whenever xn ® l in X, then f(xn) ® f(l) in Y.
In each case above, it is routine to prove the statement true in a general topological space as asserted. We illustrate by proving Theorem 3.1:
Let f be continuous and xn ® l in X. We must show that f(xn) ® f(l). Given a neighbourhood N of f(l), there exists open G such that f(l) Î G Í N. Then l Î f-1(G) Í f-1(N) i.e. f-1(N) is a neighbourhood of l and so xn Î f-1(N) "n ³ n0 say. Thus f(xn) Î N "n ³ n0, whence f(xn) ® f(l).
In metric spaces, the converses of these results are also true but our main point here is that in general topology, the converses are not valid.
Example
In (R, L), [`(0,1)] = R. So, for example, 5 Î [`(0,1)] and yet the only way a sequence (xn) converges to a limit
l is for xn = l from some stage on. So no sequence in (0,1)
can converge to 5 proving that the converse of Theorem 3.1 is false.
Continuing, the limit of any convergent sequence in (0,1) must belong to (0,1) for the same reason and yet (0,1) is not closed. Thus, Theorem 3.1's converse is false.
Further, idR:(R, L) ® (R, Á) is not continuous and yet it does preserve limits of sequences.
Now this is a great nuisance! Sequences are of immense usefulness in real analysis and in metric spaces and elsewhere - and their failure to describe general topology adequately is a technical handicap. What to do?
Recall that a sequence is just a function having the positive integers as domain. The set of positive integers, of course, possesses a particularly simple ordering; there is a first member, second member, third member, etc. Not all sets are naturally endowed with so simple an ordering. For example, dictionary (lexographical) ordering of words is more complex (though still relative nice as orderings go). By replacing the domain of positive integers with a set having a more complicated ordering we will:
Note that these last two items generalize the role of sequences in a metric space.
Definition 1
A binary relation £ on a set P is said to be a pre-order iff
(i) p £ p "p Î P
(ii) p £ q and q £ r imply p £ r "p,q,r Î P.
If it is also true that for p,q Î P,
{\em (iii)} p £ q and q £ p imply p = q, P is said to be a
partially ordered set (or poset).
Definition 2 A pre-ordered set P is said to be directed (or updirected) iff each pair of members of P has an upperbound.
(i.e. if p,q Î P, then there exists s Î P such that p £ s, q £ s.)
Definition 3
Let (P, £ ) be a poset. Then if x,y Î P with x \not £ y and
y \not £ x, we write x ||y and say that x and y are
incomparable;
If E Í P, then E is said to be totally unordered (or diverse)
iff x,y Î E implies x = y or x ||y.
If C Í P, then C is said to be linear (or a chain or
a total order) iff x,y Î C implies x < y, x = y or y < x.
(P, £ ) is said to be a lattice iff each pair of members of P
has a greatest lower bound and a least upper bound.
A lattice (P, £ ) is said to be complete iff every non-empty
subset Y of P has a greatest lower bound (ÙY) and a least upper
bound (ÚY).
An element v of a poset (P, £ ) is said to be maximal
( minimal) iff v £ x (x £ v), x Î P Þ v = x.
Definition 4 A net in a (non-empty set) X is any function x:A ® X whose domain A is a directed set.
In imitation of the familiar notation in sequences, we usually write the net value x(a) as xa. A typical net x:A ® X will usually appear as (xa, a Î A) or (xa)a Î A or some such notation.
(i)
N, Z, N ×N are all directed sets, where suitable
pre-orders are respectively the usual magnitude ordering for N and Z,
and (i,j) £ (m,n) iff i £ m and j £ n, in N ×N.
Thus, for example, a sequence is an example of a net.
(ii)
The real function f:R \{0} ® R given by
f(x) = 3-[1/x] is a net, since its domain is a chain. Any
real function is a net.
(iii)
Given x Î (X, T), select in any fashion an element
xN from each neighbourhood N of x; then (xN)N Î Nx
is a net in X ( since it defines a mapping from (Nx, £ )
into X). Recall that Nx is ordered by inverse set inclusion!
Definition 5 A net (xa)a Î A in (X, T) converges to a limit l if for each neighbourhood N of l, there exists some aN Î A such that xa Î N for all a ³ aN.
In such a case, we sometimes say that the net (xa)a Î A
eventuates N. Clearly, this definition incorporates the old definition of `limit of a sequence'. The limit of the net f described in (ii) above is 3. In (iii), the net described converges to x no matter how the values xN are chosen ... prove!
Our claim is that nets `fully describe' the structure of a topological space. Our first piece of evidence to support this is that with nets, instead of sequences, Theorems 3.1, 3.1 and 3.1 have workable converses:
Theorem 4 Given (X,T), A Í X, p Î X: p Î [`A] iff there exists a net in A converging to p.
Proof If some net of points of A converges to p, then every neighbourhood of p contains points of A (namely, values of the net) and so we get p Î [`A]. Conversely, if p is a closure point of A then, for each neighbourhood N of p, it will be possible to choose an element aN of A that belongs also to N. The net which these choices constitute converges to p, as required.
Theorem 5 Given (X,T), A Í X, A is closed iff it contains every limit of every (convergent) net of its own points.
Proof This is really just a corollary of the preceding theorem.
Theorem 6 Given f:(X,T) ® (Y,T¢), f is continuous iff f preserves net convergence.
Proof Exercise.
Definition 6 Let (xa)a Î A be any net and let a0 Î A. The a0th tail of the net is the set {xa: a ³ a0} = x([a0, )). We denote it by x(a0 ®).
Definition 7
Let (xa)a Î A and (yb)b Î B be any two nets.
We call (yb)b Î B a subnet of (xa)a Î A
provided that every tail of (xa) contains a tail of (yb) i.e.
provided:
"a0 Î A $b0 Î B such that x(a0 ®) Ê y(b0 ®).
We expected a definition like `subsequence' to turn up here and we are disappointed that it has to be so complicated.
Net theory ceases to be a straightforward generalisation of sequence theory precisely when we have to take a subnet ... so we'll try to avoid this whenever possible! There is however one result certainly worth knowing:
Theorem 7 (X, T) is compact iff in X, every net has (at least one) convergent subnet.
(So, for example, (n) is a net in R with no convergent subnet.)
Proof Not required.
Corollary 1 Compactness is closed-hereditary
Proof (for if (xa) is a net in a closed set F Í X, then it has a convergent subnet (yb) in X. Thus there exists a subnet (zg) of (yb) in F which converges in X, whence its limit is in F).
Corollary 2 Compactness is preserved by continuous maps
Proof (for if X is compact and f continuous, let (ya)a Î A be a net in f(X). Then for each a Î A, ya = f(xa) for some xa Î X. The net (xa)a Î A has a convergent subnet (zb)b Î B, say zb ® l, whence f(zb) ® f(l). Then (f(zb))b Î B is a convergent subnet of (ya)a Î A).
Example
If (xnk) is a subsequence of a sequence (xn), then it is a subnet of
it also; because the i0th tail of the sequence (xn) is
|
|
Lemma 1 If a net (xa) converges to a limit l, then so do all its subnets.
Proof Let (yb) be a subnet of (xa); let N be a neighbourhood of l. Then there exists a0 such that xa Î N for all a ³ a0. Further, there exists b0 such that {yb: b ³ b0} Í {xa:a ³ a0} and so yb Î N for all b ³ b0.
Definition 8 Let x Î (X, T). A countable neighbourhood base at x means: a sequence N1, N2, N3, ... of particular neighbourhoods of x such that every neighbourhood of x shall contain one of the Ni's.
Note that we may assume that N1 Ê N2 Ê N3 Ê ¼ because, if not, then we can work with N1, N1 ÇN2, N1 ÇN2 ÇN3, ...
Definition 9 We call (X, T) first-countable when every point in X has a countable neighbourhood base.
Example The classic example of a first-countable space is any metric (or metrizable) space because if x Î (M,d), then B(x,1), B(x, [1/2]), B(x, [1/3]), ... is a countable neighbourhood base at x.
Theorem 8 First-countability is hereditary and preserved by continuous open onto maps.
Proof Left to the reader.
Theorem 9
(i) Complete separability implies first countability.
(ii) Converse not always true.
(iii) Converse valid on a countable underlying set.
(i) If B is a countable base for (X, T) and p Î X,
consider { B Î B: p Î B} which is a countable family of
neighbourhoods of p. Moreover, they form a neighbourhood base at p.
(ii) An uncountable discrete space is first countable ( since metrizable),
yet is not completely separable.
(iii) Suppose X countable and (X, T) first countable. For
each x Î X, choose a countable neighbourhood base: N(x,1), N(x,2),
N(x,3), .... Each is a neighbourhood of x and so contains an open
neighbourhood of x: G(x,1), G(x,2), G(x,3), ....
Then B = { G(x,n) :n Î N, x Î X} is a countable family of open sets and is a base for (X, T). Thus, (X, T) is completely separable.
Example
The Arens-Fort space (see, for example, Steen and Seebach, Counterexamples
in Topology is not first-countable because otherwise it would be
completely separable which is false!
Theorem 10
Given a first-countable space (X, T)
(i) p Î X, A Í X, then p Î [`A] iff there exists
a sequence of points of A converging to p.
(ii) A Í X is closed iff A contains every limit of every
convergent sequence of its own points.
(iii) f:(X,T) ® (Y,T¢) is continuous iff
it preserves limits of (convergent) sequences.
(i) Theorem 3.1 said that if there exists a sequence in A converging to some
p Î X, then p Î [`A].
Conversely, if p Î [`A], then p has a countable base of
neighbourhoods N1 Ê N2 Ê N3 Ê ¼, each of
which must intersect A. So choose xj Î Nj ÇA for all j ³ 1.
Then (xj) is a sequence in A and, given any neighbourhood H of p,
H must contain one of the Nj's i.e. H Ê Nj0 Ê Nj0 + 1 Ê ¼ so that xj Î H for all j ³ j0.
That is, xj ® p.
(ii) Corollary of (i).
(iii) f continuous implies that it must preserve limits of sequences
(by Theorem 3.1). Conversely, if f is not continuous, there exists A Í X such that f([`A]) \not Í [`f(A)]. Thus,
there exists p Î f([`A]) \[`f(A)] so p = f(x), some
x Î [`A]. So there exists a sequence (xn) in A with xn ® x.
Yet, if f(xn) ® f(x) ( = p), p would be the limit of a sequence in f(A) so that p Î [`f(A)] -contradiction! Thus f fails to preserve convergence of this sequence.
A common task in topology is to construct new topological spaces from other spaces. One way of doing this is by taking products. All are familiar with identifying the plane or 3-dimensional Euclidean space with ordered pairs or triples of numbers each of which is a member of the real line. Fewer are probably familar with realizing the torus as ordered pairs of complex numbers of modulus one. In this chaper we answer two questions:
The process of constructing a product falls naturally into two stages.
Suppose throughout that we are given a family of topological spaces {(Xi, Ti): i Î I } where I is some non-empty `labelling' or index set.
Our first task is to get a clear mental picture of what we mean by the product of the sets Xi. Look again at the finite case where I = {1,2, ¼,n}. Here, the product set
|
|
Then a typical element of X = ÕXi will look like: (xi)i Î I or just (xi). We will still call xi the ith coordinate of (xi)i Î I. ( Note that the Axiom of Choice assures us that ÕXi is non-empty provided none of the Xi's are empty.)
Definition 1 For each i Î I, the ith projection is the map pi:ÕXi ® Xi which `selects the ith coordinate' i.e. pi((xi)i Î I) = xi.
An open cylinder means the inverse projection of some non-empty Ti-open set i.e. pi-1(Gi) where i Î I, Gi ¹ Æ, Gi Î Ti.
An open box is the intersection of finitely many open cylinders Çj = 1n pij-1(Gij).
The only drawable case I = {1,2} may help explain:
(Here will be, eventually, a picture!)
We use these open cylinders and boxes to generate a topology with just enough open sets to guarantee that projection maps will be continuous. Note that the open cylinders form a subbase for a certain topology T on X = ÕXi and therefore the open boxes form a base for T; T is called the [Tychonoff]product topology and (X, T) is the product of the given family of spaces. We write (X,T) = Õ{ (Xi, Ti): i Î I } = Õi Î I(Xi, Ti) or even T = Õi Î ITi.
Notice that if Çj = 1npij-1(Gij) is any open box, then without loss of generality we can assume i1, i2, ... in all different because if there were repetitions like
|
|
It is routine to check that if Tn is the usual topology on Rn, and T the usual topology on R, then
|
Lemma 1 In a product space (X, T), N is a neighbourhood of p Î X iff there exists some open box B such that p Î B Í N.
Lemma 2
For each i Î I,
(i) pi is continuous
(ii) pi is an open mapping.
(i) Immediate.
(ii) Given open G Í X, then G is a union of basic open sets
{Bk:k Î K} in X, whence pi(G) is a union of open subsets
{Bki:k Î K} of Xi and is therefore open. (The notation here is
intended to convey that Bki is the 'component along the i-th coordinate
axis' of the open box Bk.)
Theorem 1 A map into a product space is continuous iff its composite with each projection is continuous.
Proof Since the projections are continuous, so must be their composites with any continuous map. To establish the converse, first show that if S is a subbase for the codomain (target) of a mapping f, then f will be continuous provided that the preimage of every member of S is open; now use the fact that the open cylinders constitute a subbase for the product topology.
Worked example Show that (X, T) ×(Y, S) is homeomorphic
to (Y, S) ×(X, T).
Solution
Define
f:X ×Y ® Y ×X and
g:Y ×X ® X ×Y
by
f(x,y) = (y,x) and
g(y,x) = (x,y).
Clearly these are one-one, onto and mutually inverse. It will suffice to
show that both are continuous.
p1°f = p2¢; p2°f = p1¢. Now pi¢ is continuous for i = 1,2 and so f is continuous! Similarly, g is continuous.
Worked example Show that the product of infinitely many copies of
(N, D) is not locally compact.
Solution
We claim that no point has a compact neighbourhood. Suppose otherwise;
then there exists p Î X, C Í X and G Í X with
C compact, G open and p Î G Í C. Pick an open box B such
that p Î B Í G Í C. B looks like Çj = 1npij-1(Gij). Choose in+1 Î I \{i1,i2, ¼,in};
then pin+1(C) is compact (since compactness is preserved by
continuous maps).
Thus, pin+1 Î pin+1(B) = Xin+1 Í pin+1(C) Í Xin+1 = (N, D). Thus, pin+1(C) = (N, D) ¼ which is not compact!
Theorem 2 Any product of connected spaces must be connected.
Proof is left to the reader.
Theorem 3 [Tychonoff's theorem] Any product of compact spaces is compact i.e. compactness is productive.
Proof It suffices to prove that any covering of X by open cylinders has a finite subcover. Suppose not and let C be a family of open cylinders which covers X but for which no finite subcover exists. For each i Î I, consider
|
|
To prove the above without Alexander's Subbase Theorem is very difficult in general, but it is fairly simple in the special case where I is finite. Several further results show that various topological properties are 'finitely productive' in this sense.
Theorem 4 If (X1, T1), (X2, T2), ..., (Xn, Tn) are finitely many sequentially compact spaces, then their product is sequentially compact.
Proof
Take any sequence (xn) Î X. The sequence ( p1(xn))n ³ 1
in sequentially compact X1 has a convergent subsequence p1(xnk) ® l1 Î X1. The sequence (p2(xnk))k ³ 1 in
sequentially compact X2 has a convergent subsequence
(p2(xnkj))j ³ 1 ® l2 Î X2 and
p1(xnkj) ® l1 also.
Do this n times! We get a subsequence (yp)p ³ 1 of the original sequence such that pi(yp) ® li for i = 1,2, ¼, n. It's easy to check that yp ® (l1, l2, ¼, ln) so that X is sequentially compact, as required.
Lemma 3 `The product of subspaces is a subspace of the product.'
Proof
Let (X, T) = Õi Î I(Xi, Ti); let Æ Ì Yi Í Xi for each i Î I. There appear to be two
different ways to topologise ÕYi:
{\em either} (i) give it the subspace topology induced by ÕTi
{\em or} (ii) give it the product of all the individual subspace topologies
(Ti)Yi.
The point is that these topologies coincide-if Gi0* is open in (Ti0)Yi0 where i0 Î I i.e. Gi0* = Yi0 ÇGi0 for some Gi0 Î Ti0, a typical subbasic open set for (ii) is
|
|
|
Theorem 5 Local compactness is finitely productive.
Proof
Given x = (x1,x2,¼,xn) Î (X, T) = Õi = 1n(Xi,Ti), we must show that x has a compact neighbourhood. Now,
for all i = 1, ¼, n, xi has a compact neighbourhood Ci in (Xi,Ti) so we choose Ti-open set Gi such that xi Î Gi Í Ci. Then
|
Lemma 4 [`(ÕYi)]T = Õ[`(Yi)]Ti ( in notation of previous lemma).
Proof Do it yourself! (`The closure of a product is a product of the closures.')
Theorem 6 Separability is finitely productive.
Proof
For 1 £ i £ n, choose countable Di Í Xi where [`(Di)]Ti = Xi. Consider D = D1 ×D2 ×¼×Dn = Õ1nDi, again countable. Then [`D] = [`(ÕDi)]T = Õ[`(Di)]Ti = ÕXi = X.
Notice that the converses of all such theorems are easily true. For example,
Theorem 7
If (X, T) = Õi Î I(Xi, Ti) is
then so is every `factor space' (Xi, Ti).
(i) compact
(ii) sequentially compact
(iii) locally compact
(iv) connected
(v) separable
(vi) completely separable
Proof For each i Î I, the projection mapping pi: X ® Xi is continuous, open and onto. Thus, by previous results, the result follows.
We have observed instances of topological statements which, although true for all metric (and metrizable) spaces, fail for some other topological spaces. Frequently, the cause of failure can be traced to there being `not enough open sets' (in senses to be made precise). For instance, in any metric space, compact subsets are always closed; but not in every topological space, for the proof ultimately depends on the observation
`given x ¹ y, it is possible to find disjoint open sets G and H with x Î G and y Î H'
which is true in a metric space (e.g. put G = B(x,e), H = B(y,e) where e = [1/2] d(x,y)) but fails in, for example, a trivial space (X, T0).
What we do now is to see how `demanding certain minimum levels-of-supply of open sets' gradually eliminates the more pathological topologies, leaving us with those which behave like metric spaces to a greater or lesser extent.
Definition 1 A topological space (X,T) is T1 if, for each x in X, {x} is closed.
Comment 1
(i) Every metrizable space is T1
(ii) (X,T0) isn't T1 unless |X| = 1
(i) T1 is hereditary
(ii) T1 is productive
(iii) T1 Þ every finite set is closed. More precisely,
(X, T) is T1 iff T Ê C, i.e. C
is the weakest of all the T1 topologies that can be defined on X.
The respects in which T1-spaces are `nicer' than others are mostly concerned with `cluster point of a set' (an idea we have avoided!). We show the equivalence, in T1 spaces, of the two forms of its definition used in analysis.
Theorem 2
Given a T1 space (X,T), p Î X and A Í X, the
following are equivalent:
(i) Every neighbourhood of p contains infinitely many points of
A
(ii) Every neighbourhood of p contains at least one point of A
different from p.
Hence, (i) Û (ii).
Definition 2 A topological space (X,T) is T2 (or Hausdorff) iff given x ¹ y in X, $ disjoint neighbourhoods of x and y.
Comment 2
(i) Every metrizable space is T2
(ii) T2 Þ T1 (i.e. any T2 space is T1,
for if x, y Î T2 X and y Î [`{x}], then every
neighbourhood of y contains x, whence x = y.)
(iii) (X,C), with X infinite, cannot be T2
(i) T2 is hereditary
(ii) T2 is productive.
{i} The proof is left to the reader.
{ii} Let (X, T) = Õi Î I(Xi, Ti) be any product
of T2 spaces. Let x = (xi)i Î I and y = (yi)i Î I be
distinct elements of X. Then there exists i0 Î I such that
xi0 ¹ yi0 in Xi0. Choose disjoint open sets G,
H in (Xi0, Ti0) so that xi0 Î G, yi0 Î H. Then x Î pi0-1(G) Î T, y Î pi0-1(H) Î T and since G ÇH = Æ, pi0-1(G)Çpi0-1(H) = Æ. Hence result.
Theorem 4 In a T2-space (X, T), if C is a compact set and x \not Î C, then there exist T-open sets G and H so that x Î G, C Í H and G ÇH = Æ.
Proof A valuable exercise: separate each point of C from x using disjoint open sets, note that the open neighbourhoods of the various elements of C, thus obtained, make up an open covering of C, reduce it to a finite subcover by appealing to compactness ...
Corollary 1 In a T2-space, any compact set is closed.
Corollary 2 In a T2-space, if C and K are non-empty compact and disjoint, then there exist open G, H such that C Í G, K Í H and G ÇH = Æ.
A basic formal distinction between algebra and topology is that although the inverse of a one-one, onto group homomorphism [etc!] is automatically a homomorphism again, the inverse of a one-one, onto continuous map can fail to be continuous. It is a consequence of Corollary 5.2 that, amongst compact T2 spaces, this cannot happen.
Theorem 5 Let f:(X1,T1) ® (X2,T2) be one-one, onto and continuous, where X1 is compact and X2 is T2. Then f is a homeomorphism.
Proof It suffices to prove that f is closed. Given closed K Í X1, then K is compact whence f(K) is compact and so f(K) is closed. Thus f is a closed map.
Theorem 6 (X,T) is T2 iff no net in X has more than one limit.
Proof
(i) $\Rightarrow$ (ii): Let x ¹ y in X; by hypothesis, there exist
disjoint neighbourhoods U of x, V of y. Since a net cannot eventually
belong to each of two disjoint sets, it is clear that no net in X can
converge to both x and y.
(ii) $\Rightarrow$ (i): Suppose that (X, T) is not Hausdorff
and that x ¹ y are points in X for which every neighbourhood of x
intersects every neighbourhood of y. Let Nx (Ny) be the
neighbourhood systems at x (y) respectively. Then both Nx and
Ny are directed by reverse inclusion. We order the Cartesian
product Nx ×Ny by agreeing that
|
|
Corollary 3 Let f:(X1, T1) ® (X2, T2), g:(X1, T1) ® (X2, T2) be continuous where X2 is T2. Then their `agreement set' is closed i.e. A = {x:f(x) = g(x)} is closed.
Definition 3
A space (X, T) is called T3 or regular provided :-
(i) it is T1, and
(ii) given x \not Î closed F, there exist disjoint open
sets G and H so that x Î G, F Í H.
(i) Every metrizable space is T3; for it is certainly T1 and
given x \not Î closed F, we have x Î open X \F so there exists e > 0 so that x Î B(x, e) Í X \F. Put G = B(x, [(e)/2]) and H = { y :d(x,y) > [(e)/2] }; the result now follows.
(ii) Obviously T3 Þ T2.
(iii) One can devise examples of T2 spaces which are not T3.
(iv) It's fairly routine to check that T3 is productive and hereditary.
(v) Warning: Some books take T3 to mean Definition 5.3(ii)
alone, and regular to mean Definition 5.3(i) and (ii);
others do exactly the opposite!
Definition 4
A space (X, T) is T3[1/2] or completely
regular or Tychonoff iff
(i) it is T1, and
(ii) given x Î X, closed non-empty F Í X such that
x \not Î F, there exists continuous f:X ® [0,1] such that
f(F) = {0} and f(x) = 1.
(i) Every metrizable space is T3[1/2]
(ii) Every T3[1/2] space is T3 ( such a space is certainly
T1 and given x \not Î closed F, choose f as in the definition;
define G = f-1([0, [1/3])), H = f-1(([2/3],1]) and observe
that T3 follows.)
(iii) Examples are known of T3 spaces which fail to be Tychonoff
(iv) T3[1/2] is productive and hereditary.
Definition 5
A space (X, T) is T4 or normal if
(i) it is T1, and
(ii) given disjoint non-empty closed subsets A, B of X, there
exist disjoint open sets G, H such that A Í G, B Í H.
Proof Certainly, X is T1; choose a metric d on X such that T is Td. The distance of a point p from a non-empty set A can be defined thus:
|
G = {x:d(x, A) < d(x,B) }
H = {x:d(x,B) < d(x,A)}.
Clearly, G ÇH = Æ. Also, each is open (if x Î G and e = [1/2]{d(x,B) - d(x,A)}, then B(x,e) Í G, by the triangle inequality.) Now, if d(p, A) = 0, then for all n Î N, there exists xn Î A such that d(p, xn) < [1/n]. So d(p,xn)® 0 i.e. xn ® p, whence p Î [`A]. Thus for each x Î A, x \not Î B = [`B] so that d(x, B) > 0 = d(x,A) i.e. x Î G. Hence A Í G. Similarly B Í H.
It's true that T4 Þ T3[1/2] but not very obvious. First note that if G0, G1 are open in a T4 space with [`(G0)] Í G1, then there exists open G[1/2] with [`(G0)] Í G[1/2] and [`(G[1/2])] Í G1 (because the given [`(G0)] and X \G1 are disjoint closed sets so that there exist disjoint open sets G[1/2], H such that [`(G0)] Í G[1/2], X\G1 Í H i.e. G1 Ê (closed) X\H Ê G[1/2]).
Lemma 1 [Urysohn's Lemma] Let F1, F2 be disjoint non-empty closed subsets of a T4 space; then there exists a continuous function f:X ® [0,1] such that f(F1) = {0}, f(F2) = {1}.
Proof Given disjoint closed F1 and F2, choose disjoint open G0 and H0 so that F1 Í G0, F2 Í H0. Define G1 = X \F2 (open). Since G0 Í (closed) X \H0 Í X \F2 = G1, we have [`(G0)] Í G1.
By the previous remark, we can now construct:
(i) G[1/2] Î T: [`(G0)] Í G[1/2], [`(G[1/2])] Í G1.
(ii) G[1/4], G[3/4] Î T:
[`(G0)] Í G[1/4], [`(G[1/4])] Í G[1/2], [`(G[1/2])] Í G[3/4], [`(G[3/4])] Í G1.
(iii) ... and so on!
Thus we get an indexed family of open sets
|
Observe that the index set is dense in [0,1]: if s < t in [0,1], there exists some [m/(2n)] such that s < [m/(2n)] < t. Define
|
Well, f(x) < a iff there exists some r = [m/(2n)] such that f(x) < r < a. It follows that f-1([0, a)) = Èr < aGr, a union of open sets.
Again, f(x) > a iff there exist r1, r2 such that a < r1 < r2 < f(x), implying that x \not Î Gr2 whence x \not Î [`(Gr1)]. It follows that f-1((a,1]) = Èr1 > a(X \[`(Gr1)]), which is again open.
Corollary 4 Every T4 space is T3[1/2].
Proof Immediate from Lemma 5.5. (Note that there exist spaces which are T3[1/2] but not T4.)
Theorem 8 Any compact T2 space is T4.
Proof Use Corollary 5.2 to Theorem 5.2.
Note Unlike the previous axioms, T4 is neither hereditary
nor productive. The global view of the hierarchy can now be filled in as an
exercise from data supplied above:-
Metrizable | Hereditary? | Productive? |
T4 | ||
T3[1/2] | ||
T3 | ||
T2 | ||
T1 |
The following is presented as an indication of how close we are to having `come full circle'.
Theorem 9 Any completely separable T4 space is metrizable!
Sketch Proof
Choose a countable base; list as { (Gn,Hn): n ³ 1} those pairs of
elements of the base for which [`(Gn)] Í Hn. For each
n, use Lemma 5.5 to get continuous fn:X ® [0,1] such
that fn([`(Gn)]) = {0}, fn(X \Hn) = {1}. Define
|